From The Worthy House on January 21, 2019
Eumeswil (by Ernst Jünger)
Ernst Jünger’s Eumeswil, one of the famous German’s last works, published when he was eighty-two years old, is often regarded as an exposition of libertarian thought. This is understandable, but completely wrong. Such a reading attempts to shoehorn concepts in which Jünger had little interest, or toward which he was actively hostile, into an exploration of unrelated themes. Moreover, it ignores that in this book, though somewhat masked, Jünger has more contempt for so-called liberal democracy than dislike for what some call tyranny. Thus, this book is not a call to rework society, or individual thought, along libertarian lines. It is instead a call for human excellence, and a criticism of the modern West for failure to achieve it, or to even try.
One cannot really understand Eumeswil without reading, preferably first reading, Jünger’s earlier The Forest Passage, which was published in 1951, twenty-six years before Eumeswil. On the surface, they are very different—this book is cast as dystopian science fiction, and The Forest Passage
is a work of philosophical exposition. But Jünger himself explicitly
ties the two books together, linking the earlier book’s concept of the
“forest rebel” with this book’s concept of the “anarch.” In both books,
the author’s focus on freedom, specific to each individual, is easily
misinterpreted, because what freedom means to most people today is not
what Jünger means by the term. Jünger means an internal, spiritual
freedom, an elitist freedom, not the freedom of license and consequent ennui. This confusion drives all the misunderstandings of Eumeswil.
While they fit together, a key difference between the books is often,
or always, overlooked. Both are analyses of how a man should live under
tyranny. But the tyrannies to which the protagonist in each book reacts
are completely different. Thus, while there are some differences
between the forest rebel and the anarch, those differences are best
explained not by developments in Jünger’s thought, but by the
differences in the tyrannies examined in each book. That is to say,
Jünger is looking at a general problem of stifled freedom from two
radically different angles—in the earlier book, from the perspective of
those trapped by Communism or other totalitarian ideologies; in the
later book, from those trapped in a much different type of tyranny, one
into which Jünger saw the West decaying, having nothing to do with
Communism. It is the difference between 1951 and 1977, one which often
escapes us now, but was very evident to a person of the time, and should
be even more evident to us today, since the defects found in 1977 in
bud form are now in full and poisonous flower, while the evils of 1951 have disappeared entirely.
Not much actually happens, plot-wise, in Eumeswil. Most of
the book consists of the private musings of the protagonist, Martin
Venator. He lives in the city-state of Eumeswil, somewhere in today’s
Morocco, after an unspecified global apocalypse some time before. (The
name comes from Eumenes, the most clever of the Diadochi, the
“successors” of Alexander, who fought over and divided his empire.
The theme of such decline is everywhere in this book, starting with the
city name itself.) Eumeswil is ruled by a man referred to only as the
Condor, a soldier who overthrew the “tribunes,” the leading men of a
broad oligarchic and quasi-democratic order, the “republic,” whose
adherents viewed, and still view, themselves as beneficent and liberal,
in contrast to the Condor, whom they naturally loathe.
Venator, a young man, has two jobs. By day he is a historian, or
rather some type of graduate student; by night he tends bar in the
Condor’s palace, at the Condor’s private bar. This permits him to
observe the Condor and his aides, as they interact and discuss both high
and low events. In Venator’s dispassionate telling, the Condor and his
men are far from fiends; they are competent and genial men, highly
intelligent and rational, concerned mostly with possible rebellions in
the city, maintaining order, keeping the people happy, and not getting
on the wrong side of people more powerful than they. Of those latter,
there are really two—the Yellow Khan, apparently either a very powerful
neighbor or some sort of overlord, who sometimes comes for state visits
that are a combination of pleasure and peril for the Condor and his men;
and the vague “catacombs,” subterranean realms of some kind from which
come advanced technology, still being developed by unspecified people,
not unearthed from dead ones. To accompany these external forces, to the
south, across the desert, lies the “Forest,” a mutated, wild land, to
which (spoiler alert) at the end of the book the Condor leads an
expedition, joined by Venator, and none of them are ever heard from
again.
Under both the tribunes and the Condor, Eumeswil is a place that is
waiting, passing the time, forever, so far as can be seen. There are no
grand plans or any real hope for the future. Here, at the end of all
things, not much happens. Perhaps it will come around again, though
there is no sign of it. (As M. John Harrison says of “defeated, resigned
landscapes” in The Pastel City,
“Or was it just waiting to be born? Who can tell at which end of Time
these places have their existence?”) Those in Eumeswil birth few
children; two maximum, not by law but because people can’t be bothered
and see no reason to have more children. Abortion is illegal but ignored
in practice, along with other vices, such as pederasty and drug use.
From a libertarian perspective, pretty much everyone is free to do as he
wants, as long as he does not overtly upset the public order (and does
not challenge the ruler, on whom more later). History is mostly ignored;
the entire society smacks of what is today called postmodernism. In
other words, Eumeswil is a stand-in for the modern West, and its people,
regardless of their formal type of government, are not analogous to
those under Communism in The Forest Passage, but to Jünger’s West German compatriots of the 1970s.
Martin’s father and brother do not approve either of his job with the
Condor or of his disinterest in politics. They were prominent partisans
of the tribunes, although they were not punished upon their overthrow.
(It is not even very risky to oppose the Condor, who executes nobody
except a handful of criminals, and governs with a very light touch,
though he does exile the most problematic dissidents to offshore
islands.) They talk politics incessantly, making family dinners
unpleasant, while they hedge their bets, preen themselves, and do
nothing, just like all their class. Venator has little sympathy with
them (exacerbated by, as he repeatedly notes, his father unsuccessfully
having tried to get his mother to kill him in the womb), but fulfils his
filial and family obligations. Venator’s repeated references to his
father’s attempts to kill him do not seem incidental; what Jünger
appears to be saying is that men like Venator’s father, supposedly
devoted to freedom, are in fact mediocrities with no future, happy to
serve their own interests (“his rights,” as Venator bitterly calls his
father’s attempt to murder him) when push comes to shove, and afraid to
take responsibility or take action. They are, thus, the opposite of the
forest rebel.
Venator respects the Condor; he has nothing but a distant contempt
for the tribunes, even though they seemed to offer more political
freedom. They “had stylized the word ‘human’ into a sublime concept.”
But their lofty ideals “all cost money, which, however, they collected
from concrete and not ideal human beings.” The tribunes, moreover, were
addicted to regulation, such as forbidding private collection of salt so
as to maintain their tax revenue, “patrolling by customs inspectors,
who ambushed the poor.” They even required the salt sold in government
stores to have “mixed in additives that their chemists praised as
useful, even though they were injurious. The fact that men with such
minds consider themselves thinkers is forgivable; but they also claim to
be benefactors.” Worst of all, the tribunes offered, if not utopias,
abstract visions. “ ‘There is no progress,’ I often hear my [father]
say; he seems to regard this is a misfortune. He also says, ‘Standing
still means going backward.’ The little people, in contrast, are
satisfied if everyday life remains constant; they prefer to see their
chimneys smoking, not their houses.” The type of progress that Venator’s
father looks for, in other words, is not progress at all, but false
forward movement paid for by others.
Much of the book is taken up with disjointed thoughts, ranging from
discussions of how the Condor’s palace, or citadel, the Casbah, is
situated a few miles outside the city (complete with references to Machiavelli on
such placements), to talk of Venator’s girlfriend, to lengthy
expositions of the thought of Venator’s various teachers. To make sense
of Eumeswil, you have to pay close attention, pick out, and
weave together what Venator says. The only steady and obvious thread is
that he clearly and repeatedly identifies himself as an “anarch”; we can
presume, I think, that Venator is here a stand-in for Jünger himself.
“Such is the role of the anarch, who remains free of all commitments yet
can turn in any direction.” The anarch is emphatically not an
anarchist. The anarchist is focused on overthrowing the existing order,
which inevitably leads to its replacement by something not to the
anarchist’s taste. The anarch’s goal is, on the contrary, to remain
aloof from all political systems. He obeys the law of the state, just as
he obeys, automatically, the laws of nature. His internal freedom is
what matters.
This concept, of internal freedom, is as far as most mention of Eumeswil
ever gets. Venator says, “I am an anarch in space, a metahistorian in
time. Hence I am committed to neither the political present nor
tradition; I am blank and also open and potent in any direction.” He
does not oppose the rules of the society in which he lives. “One must
know the rules, whether one is moving in a tyranny, a demos, or a
bordello. This holds, above all, for the anarch—it is the second
commandment, next to the first: ‘Know thyself.’ ” Usually, this
conception gets a nod as a type of pure, Zen-like freedom: the sovereign
individual, keeping himself internally liberated, but not choosing to
fight for formal freedom in the temporal realm. In other words, as with The Forest Passage,
a common present-day interpretation of Jünger’s politics is as
libertarian—the freedom to do as one chooses, which is what we would
have if everyone could take the actions that germinate in an anarch’s
head. This is completely wrong. Jünger is instead pushing an elite
freedom, the freedom to avoid the mediocrity and oppression of the
collective, not the freedom to do as one pleases. The anarch can move in
any direction, true, but to what end?
It is the petty and controlling, fake benefactory and semi-utopian,
nature of the tribunes to which Venator objects, rather than to their
laws as such. The key is that he rejects the tearing down of authority.
“Although an anarch, I am not anti-authoritarian. Quite the opposite: I
need authority, although I do not believe in it.” Those would who have
unbridled freedom are parasitical and destructive. “Why do people who
leave nothing unchallenged still make demands of their own? They live
off the fact that gods, fathers, and poets used to exist. . . . In the
animal kingdom, there are parasites that clandestinely hollow out a
caterpillar. Eventually, a mere wasp emerges instead of a butterfly. And
that is what those people do with their heritage, and with language in
particular.” That’s what Jünger really thinks of libertarians, and it’s
not pretty. And for the same reasons, Jünger pretty obviously had no use
for what liberal democracy has become, with its closely related
destructive rush to atomized freedom and total emancipation.
Most of all, Venator objects to the tribunes’ utopian schemes.
Remember, in my reading, the tribunes, and Eumeswil itself, are
stand-ins for the modern society of the West, which by the 1970s was
offering so-called liberal democracy as a utopian panacea, with an
insufferable smugness that reached its high point only a few years later
in Francis’s Fukuyama’s “end of history.” Jünger, a man who lived
through all the horrors the twentieth century had to offer, had no
interest in offering utopias, whether political or philosophical, and
had seen first-hand who pays the price for dreams of false progress. At
an early age, Venator, and doubtless his alter-ego, Jünger, “formed
[his] conviction of the imperfect and peaceless nature of the world.”
Given that conviction, all utopias are a mistake, because they are
impossible, and only result in misery. Along these same lines, Venator
endorses the core idea of Carl Schmitt
that pinning rationales for war on utopian visions of an abstract
humanity, rather than a recognition of who the enemy is by nature,
results in far worse killing. “If humanity is written on the standard,
then this means not only the exclusion of the enemy from society, but
the deprivation of all his human rights.” The implication is that for
all the supposed freedom under the tribunes, which Venator’s father and
brother claim to miss so much, it did not mean anything at all that
mattered, and cost more than it brought.
On the other hand, Venator seems to have little objection to the
Condor. Yes, Venator regularly, though dispassionately, refers to the
Condor as a tyrant. But is he really? If he is, he has nothing to do
with modern totalitarianisms. More than once Venator ties him to
Periander, the Tyrant of Corinth who died in 585 B.C. Periander was one
of the Seven Sages, men of wisdom and power, who also included Thales of
Miletus (to whom, among others, the Delphic maxim “Know thyself” is
attributed), and Solon of Athens. Eumeswil is not even a police state.
In fact, it allows all sorts of ordered freedoms, and many disordered
freedoms, within the constraints of not too directly challenging the
ruler. A modest amount of vice is allowed and it appears that there is a
sizable amount of low-level corruption greasing the skids of day-to-day
life. What shows most of all that he’s not a real tyrant is that Condor
can and does openly move around, “discreetly accompanied,” on the
public streets and the waterfront, talking to and joking with the
people, with whom he is popular. If he is a tyrant, he is a tyrant in
the mold of Augustus.
The Condor is explicitly not a despot, by which Jünger means
capricious or interested in degrading people to show his power. As far
as is evident, Eumeswil has the rule of law.
A moderately free press exists. The justice system works. “Tyranny
[i.e., the Condor] must value a sound administration of justice in
private matters. This, in turn, increases its political authority.” The
Condor does not offer any ideology and is pleased to encourage education
and what culture there is, as well as try to improve himself. “The
Condor sticks to Machiavelli’s doctrine that a good military and good
laws are the fundaments of the state.” Really, the Condor is not
dissimilar to Machiavelli’s “new
princedom,” like that of, say, Francesco Sforza (who took over Milan in
the fifteenth century). (I suspect that a close reading of The Prince with Eumeswil would
show quite a few interesting overlaps.) The Condor is fiscally prudent,
ensuring a hard money economy and restraining state spending, all of
which benefits the common people (and is in contrast to the tribunes,
who talked of the common people but despised and harmed them). Jünger
may not regard the Condor as ideal, but he regards him as having a form
of excellence, of aristocracy, and he thinks little of the mass of the
population of Eumeswil, and especially the political class of Venator’s
father and brother, where language is degraded, history is ignored, and
nobody is very interested in excellence, or, for that matter, true
freedom—all just like today’s liberal democracies, but not like
Augustan-style “tyrannies.”
Jünger makes it explicit that the anarch is the same as the forest rebel—or at least one conception of the forest rebel. In Eumeswil, however, Jünger seems less enamored of actual action by the forest rebel in The Forest Passage.
He denigrates partisan bands and other commitments to political change
(such as anarchism), as “stuffy air, unclear ideas, lethal energy, which
ultimately put abdicated monarchs and retired generals back in the
saddle—and then they show their gratitude by liquidating those selfsame
partisans.” Joining the partisans makes on dependent on them; the
anarch’s goal is to avoid dependence, even while he serves someone,
whether the Condor or someone else. “The difference is that the forest
[rebel] has been expelled from society, while the anarch has expelled
society from himself.” Really, though, that’s a distinction without a
difference, because the result is the same. Perhaps, I think, what
Jünger is saying is that under a totalitarian tyranny, that of the
forest rebel, action may make more sense (something covered in The Forest Passage
in some detail), but under the modern tyranny of liberal democracy,
action is futile, because it is not the government that is the problem,
but the society. If you extend Jünger’s line of thought, the Condor
points toward a possible solution to the flaws of liberal democracy, not
something against which rebellion is either necessary or desirable.
So what does that imply for the anarch, who can turn in any
direction, but presumably will, at some point, choose a direction?
Jünger is explicitly not a reactionary in the sense of wanting to return
to a better past. In the words of his alter-ego, “It is not that I am
awaiting a return to the past, like Chateaubriand, or a recurrence, like
Boutefeu [a Nietzsche-like figure]; I leave those matters politically
to the conservatives and cosmically to the stargazers. . . . No, I hope
for something equal, nay, stronger, and not just in the human domain. Naglfar, the ship of the apocalypse, shifts into a calculable position.” Naglfar is
the ship, in Norse mythology, that will ferry dead men to fight the
gods in the final battle, Ragnarök. That is, Jünger wants a renewal, but
he sees no way that Eumeswil can be renewed in the usual course of
life. The Condor cannot do it, nor does he try. But it is significant,
in this context, that the book ends with Venator and the Condor marching
into, and disappearing into, the Forest, seeking that which they would
find. That is, the book ends with the Condor himself turning forest
rebel. It is just as significant that Venator, the exemplar of the
anarch, chooses wholly voluntarily to accompany the Condor as his
servant, as his “Xenophon,” on this expedition. Both of them seek
excellence and a renewal of things through human action; they are the
opposite of José Ortega y Gasset’s “mass man,”
the necessary end product of liberal democracy. As one of Venator’s
teachers tells him, urging him to go, “A dream comes true in each of our
great transformations. You know this as a historian. We fail not
because of our dreams but because we do not dream forcefully enough.”
This is not the language of libertarian inertia or pleasure
maximization; it is the language of Godfrey in the gate.
Nor is it random (nothing in this book is random, even if frequently it
is opaque) that in the very brief postscript written by Venator’s
brother, committing Venator’s writing to a sealed archive (presumably
because his thought is dangerous), he says smugly, “A great deal has
changed in the city and, if I may say so, for the better. The Casbah is
now desolate; goatherds pasture their goats inside the walls of the
stronghold.” The Condor, and the anarch, may have failed in their goals,
but at least they dreamed great dreams, and, even more importantly,
took risks to achieve them, unlike the decayed people of Eumeswil, ruled
by the even more decayed class of the tribunes.
Thus, despite the common misconception (including that of the
excellent Introduction by Russell Berman), this is not a book about the
tyranny of Communism, or about tyranny in general, such as that of some
banana republic authoritarianism. It is about the specific tyranny and
flaws of liberal democracy, the fatal defects of which Jünger saw
clearly long before most. Like Václav Havel,
Jünger did not believe that liberal democracy was the solution to much
of anything, even if it was better than totalitarianism. Jünger may not
have seen, or anticipated, all the specifics of the defects of end-stage
liberal democracy, the core problem of which is Ryszard Legutko’s “coercion to freedom.” (Jünger does explicitly prefigure Legutko when he has Venator remark that in Eumeswil, “freedom was consumed for the sake of equality.”) Nor did he, at least here, narrate the inherent defects of the Enlightenment project of atomized freedom.
Presumably someone more familiar with Jünger’s voluminous output (much
of which is untranslated and which, in the German, runs to twenty-two
volumes) could offer a more precise answer, and a more precise slotting
of this book into Jünger’s thought. But still, it is fascinating that
Jünger saw our current future long before most, and, perhaps, he also
saw possible paths toward, if not finding a solution, at least
addressing the problems. Maybe that path is something less dramatic than
disappearing into the Forest—but maybe it is marching into it, for
nothing ventured, nothing gained.
No comments:
Post a Comment